Tagged: social sciences research

Negativism

Paradigm Wars

I coined the term negativists in this blog post a couple of weeks ago. This is something that I feel I am going to keep returning to over the course of the next several months, perhaps years, as I address methodology and paradigms as a part of my research. I want to explore this negativism and try to understand what drives it. I also want to explore ways that negativism can be addressed so that the idea that numbers and words cannot be friends can be addressed, which as far as I can see can only be beneficial for research.

I chose the word negativists, and its corollary negativism, to make a point about people who use the word positivist as a term of abuse. But in fact it can be applied to any vociferous methodological bloodlust that determines to hoist a paradigmatic standard and defend a corner of what some plainly believe to be an ontological and epistemological battleground.

The debate in the social sciences over ontology and epistemology has often been fraught. Both ‘sides’ of some imagined division have been deemed guilty of attempting to skewer their ‘opponents’ on charges that include gender hegemony, for example “malestream” positivism (Oakley 1998:707), or of misunderstanding the nature of evidence: “the plural of anecdote is not statistic” (Mulgan quoted in Rutter 2012:15). This “dreadful 1980s culture war” (Goldacre 2013) is irrelevant. Oakley (2000) gives an account of how actual practices in both natural and social sciences research defy the assumption that researchers occupy one of either side of a binary world of ‘quality’ or ‘quantity’, ‘interpretivism’ or ‘positivism’, ‘naturalism’ or ‘scientism’.

I reject the expectation that one must declare an adherence to either one of these positions. As both Oakley and Goldacre (and others, like Stephen Gorard) have emphasised, it is the research question which should dictate the approach to addressing it (Oakley 1999, Goldacre 2013), not some perceived membership of a paradigmatic ‘tribe’. By extension, it is the research question, setting, participants and expected outcomes that should inform the ontological assumptions informing the assessment of the external validity of any findings. Knowledge is always provisional and imperfect. If it were not so, so-called ‘positivists’ would not acknowledge the influences of placebo, Hawthorne and research participation effects (McCambridge, Kypri and Elbourne 2014). So-called ‘interpretivists’ would find their work so unique as to not have any applicability beyond the specific circumstance in which it was conducted (after Larsen-Freeman 2000). To debate the minutiae of the philosophical underpinnings informing differing world views is to split hairs. Or, to borrow from Theravada Buddhist teachings, “Conjecture about [the origin, etc., of] the world is an unconjecturable that is not to be conjectured about. That would bring madness and vexation to anyone who conjectured about it” (Acintita Sutta [AN 4.77]).

Social sciences is damaged by this attempt to make the world binary. It is damaged by the assumption that there are mutually exclusive worlds of ‘quality’ and ‘quantity’. I do everything I can to not use those words to describe the work I am interested in. Quite apart from anything, else you will find the work of self declared ‘qualitativists’ to include all sorts of ‘quantitative’ language (more, less, greater, lesser, larger, smaller, a majority, a minority) and the work of self declared ‘quantitavists’ will include all sorts of references to interpretation (we are tempted to conclude, it appears, the general trend implies).

While I have meditated on this issue for a while, this particular post was catalysed by a tweet I saw yesterday which, I think, perfectly sums up the nonsense posed by this attempt to polarise the world of social sciences research.

In response to the suggestion that we should share data, the second tweeter is seeming to suggest that, firstly, the data we collect can be too personal to share – in which case what are we doing collecting it in the first place? We are going to share this information – that’s the point of research. If we have satisfied ourselves and our informants that we will behave ethically with the data (by anonymising it, for example), why not make it available for other people to interpret or combine with other similar data in systematic reviews in the pursuit of fuller understanding? More shocking, however, is the view that replicability is somehow “a quant expectation, not qualitative”. This is demonstrable nonsense. We do research so that we can understand the world better. If this tweet represents a genuine belief that so called ‘qualitative’ research can’t or shouldn’t be replicated, then what value does that research hold, beyond the immediate context (time, place, population, etc.) in which it was conducted? If I see a study that explores Birmingham school teachers’ responses to the implementation of, say, new workload expectations, that uses an ethnographic enquiry, and the results interest me to the degree that I would like to find out how they compare to the same situation in, say, London, why on earth shouldn’t I seek to replicate? But all of that aside, the false binary being perpetrated here is that you are only allowed to do certain things with data based on whether they are numbers or words!

Negativism hurts social science. I will be returning to this theme.